Is instantenous speed a central example here? I'm asking because I'm surprised to find it's not an intuitive notion: I don't remember fellow classmates struggling with it (and I do remember struggles with abstractions such as a function that happens to be linear. I will probably ask my 6~8yr old "nephews" in the coming days; suggestions on concrete questions that show the difficulty are very welcome.)
I don't think children are likely to start with that worldview based on anecdotal evidence: I don't know anyone who initially considered Zeno's (Xeno's?) paradox to be intuitive (@timorl , did you?). When I first learned of it (sometime in primary school) it seemed contrived to me.
Oof, I wrote a long-ish response and only then remembered that this is not about that Zeno’s paradox – we are talking about the one with the arrow not moving at a specific point in time, right? The other ones always seemed to me more like jokes (i.e. subverting intuitive expectations), but this one did make some sense. Although I think rather than pointing to the difficulty in accepting instantenous speed, it points to the counterintuitive concept of considering a situation at a specific point in time altogether. I think the intuitive approach to understanding everyday mechanics is much more dynamic, and introducing any moment-by-moment abstraction requires some work, including the fact that speed is still associated with objects (even if the fact by itself is not particularly hard to accept).
But these are guesses, our current culture is soaked in this understanding of dynamics to an extent that almost surely influences children even before they get formally introduced to physics, so it’s hard to tell which things are a priori intuitive – for that you really gotta study history like @johncarlosbaez does.
@robryk @johncarlosbaez
From a certain point of view, it can seem that, instantaneously, nothing moves, therefore, how could there be speed? Zeno's paradoxes.